The Ancient Library
 

Scanned text contains errors.

On this page: Philosophy (continued)

PHILOSOPHY.

482

314). Both of them sought to fuse Pytha­gorean speculations on number with Plato’s theory of ideas. The two other Academies were still further removed from the specific doctrines of Plato (see below}.

The most important among Plato’s dis­ciples is aristotle of Stagira (384-322), who shares with his master the title of the greatest philosopher of antiquity. But whereas Plato had sought to elucidate and explain things from the suprasensual stand­point of the ideas, his pupil preferred to start from the facts given us by experience. Philosophy to him meant science, and its aim was the recognition of the "wherefore" in all things. Hence he endeavours to attain to the ultimate grounds of things by induc­tion ; that is to say, by a posteriori conclu­sions from a number of facts to a universal. In the series of works collected under the name of Orgdndn, Aristotle sets forth, almost in a final form, the laws by which the human understanding effects conclusions from the particular to the knowledge of the universal. Like Plato, he recognises the true being of things in their concepts, but denies any separate existence of the concept apart from the particular objects of sense. They are as inseparable as matter and form. In this antithesis, matter and form, Aristotle sees the fundamental prin­ciples of being. Matter is the basis of all that exists; it comprises the potentiality of everything, but of itself is not actually anything. A determinate thing only comes into being when the potentiality in matter is converted into actuality. This is effected by form, the idea existent not as oue out­side the many, but as one in the many, the completion of the potentiality latent in the matter. Although it has no existence apart from the particulars, yet, in rank and estimation, form stands first; it is of its own nature the most knowable, the only true object of knowledge. For matter without any form cannot exist, but the essential definitions of a common form, in which are included the particular objects, may be separated from matter. Form and matter are relative terms, and the lower form constitutes the matter of a higher (e.g. body, soul, reason). This series culminates in pure, immaterial form, the Deity, the origin of all motion, and therefore of the generation of actual form out of potential matter. All motion takes place in space and time; for space is the potentiality, time the measure of the motion. Living beings are those which have in them a moving

principle, or soul. In plants, the function of soul is nutrition (including reproduction); in animals, nutrition and sensation; in men, nutrition, sensation, and intellectual acti­vity. The perfect form of the human soul is reason separated from all connexion with the body, hence fulfilling its activity with­out the help of any corporeal organ, and so imperishable. By reason the apprehen­sions, which are formed in the soul by external sense-impressions, and may be true or false, are converted into knowledge. For reason alone can attain to truth either in cognition or action. Impulse towards the good is a part of human nature, and on this is founded virtue; for Aristotle does not, with Plato, regard virtue as knowledge pure and simple, but as founded on nature, habit, and reason. Of the particular virtues (of which there are as many as there are contingencies in life), each is the appre­hension, by means of reason, of the proper mean between two extremes which are not virtues; e.g. courage is the mean between cowardice and foolhardiness. The end of human activity, or the highest good, is happiness, or perfect and reasonable activity in a perfect life. To this, however, external goods are more or less necessary conditions. The followers of Aristotle, known as Peripatetics (theophrastus of Lesbos, ErjDEMUs of Rhodes, strato of Lampsacus, etc.), to a great extent abandoned meta­physical speculation, some in favour of natural science, others of a more popular treatment of ethics, introducing many changes into the Aristotelian doctrine in a naturalistic direction. A return to the views of the founder first appears among the later Peripatetics, who did good service as expositors of Aristotle‘s works. The tendency of the Peripatetic school to make philosophy the exclusive property of the learned class, thereby depriving it of its power to benefit a wider circle, soon pro­duced a reaction; and philosophers returned to the practical standpoint of Socratic ethics. The speculations of the learned were only admitted in philosophy where immediately serviceable for ethics. The chief con­sideration was how to popularise doctrines, and to provide the individual, in a time of general confusion and dissolution, with a fixed moral basis for practical life. Such were the aims of Stoicism, founded at Athens about 310 by zbno of Cittlum, and brought to fuller systematic form by his suc­cessors as heads of the school, cleanthes of AsscSs and especially chkysippus o* Soii

Pages
About | Preface | Contents | Index

vii

viii

ix
page #  
Search this site
Google


ancientlibrary.com
WWW